The solemn investigator of useless things Newsletter

Share this post

The invisible hand: The natural order of things

solemninvestigator.substack.com

The invisible hand: The natural order of things

Investigation #7

Sanjay Perera
Feb 9, 2022
1
Share this post

The invisible hand: The natural order of things

solemninvestigator.substack.com

I always assumed…that the writers we were studying were always much smarter than I was. If they were not, why was I wasting my time…studying them? If I saw a mistake in their arguments, I supposed they [the philosophers] saw it too and must have dealt with it, but where? So I looked for their way out, not mine. Sometimes their way out was historical: in their day the question need not be raised; or wouldn’t arise or be fruitfully discussed. Or there was a part of the text I had overlooked, or hadn’t read.—John Rawls, “Some Remarks About My Teaching”

by Sanjay Perera

This piece is an extract that has been edited and slightly revised from an essay of mine published over a decade ago as “There is no such thing as a free market” (in three parts). The latter was polemical but I have kept some of the tone of the original here. It is also a foundation of sorts for other pieces that will develop further the ideas here. This version is still lengthy and is best read in parts.

[Credit: Edition Originale.]

I

Enter: Adam Smith

Perhaps one of the most misunderstood thinkers  of any time has been Adam Smith. What has been done in the name of that  man is as shameful as what has been done in the name of Marx. While  Marx’s great Capital was partly a response to The Wealth of Nations (WN),  he had a much better appreciation of what Smith’s work was about than  many after him. Marx insisted that most who promoted Capitalism in  Smith’s name had misrepresented what the good Scotsman was saying. And  Marx was right on the money.

The many who are Free Market (FM) fantasists and hardcore Capitalists often thump WN as  if it were holy writ and claim the kernel of their beliefs lie in that  tome. To say that the FM, as has been discussed, was proposed by Smith  is to genetically modify his ideas into a Frankenstein monster that is  in the process of destroying its creators through the economic crisis of  our time

It is important to know that prior to writing WN, Smith had written The Theory of Moral Sentiments (TMS).  While the former is his best-known work, the latter is perhaps his  greatest work. Smith was not, thank heavens, an economist. He was a  professor of moral philosophy. Think about that: a professor of moral philosophy. Hence, a work entitled TMS.

The key ideas in TMS are worth noting. They are even crucial to a proper understanding of WN.  To Smith, human beings have sympathy with their fellow humans as in  understanding what joy and pain mean in others because they have  experienced it themselves. But there is much more to this. People have a  moral conscience and know what is right and wrong. Smith says that no  man who is himself at ease can see another on the rack and avoid  sympathy with the sufferer’s plight.

But contrary to those who adulterate Smith’s ideas, he clearly  believes in Divinity. He regularly refers to the Deity and God in TMS.  He even mentions that God looks after the Universe which is benign and  while God’s will, is beyond man’s comprehension, man is responsible for  doing what is right on earth.

Here is an important passage from TMS, VI.II.49:

The administration of the great  system of the universe, however, the care of the universal happiness of  all rational and sensible beings, is the business of God and not of man.  To man is allotted a much humbler department, but one much more  suitable to the weakness of his powers, and to the narrowness of his  comprehension; the care of his own happiness, of that of his family, his  friends, his country: that he is occupied in contemplating the more  sublime, can never be an excuse for his neglecting the more humble  department; and he must not expose himself to the charge which Avidius  Cassius is said to have brought, perhaps unjustly, against Marcus  Antoninus; that while he employed himself in philosophical speculations,  and contemplated the prosperity of the universe, he neglected that of  the Roman empire. The most sublime speculation of the contemplative  philosopher can scarce compensate the neglect of the smallest active  duty.

This is one of the clearest indications Smith gives of a moral centre  to the universe with God’s Order behind it; where man has his own  sphere of responsibility in discharging his duty on earth together with  his fellow humans in alignment with what is right. This is the grounded  viewpoint of Smith that fills not just TMS but is the basis for WN.

It is clear, that Smith believes that there is a difference between  self-interest and selfishness. He praises the former and denigrates the  obvious. In no uncertain terms does Smith condemn unbridled greed,  social injustice, anger, hatred, and all things associated with negative  human attitudes and behaviour.

Self-interested man looks after his own welfare and is always trying  to achieve his highest good in a decent, fair and reasonable manner; but  by doing so he in turn automatically, irrespective as to whether he is  conscious of it or not, serves the greater welfare and good of his  society.

Lest there still be any doubts as to Smith’s theistic views and the  role of providence in his social and economic ideas, these passages from  TMS VI.II.44-45 (bold and italics mine) should be of use:

Though our effectual good offices  can very seldom be extended to any wider society than that of our own  country; our good-will is circumscribed by no boundary, but may embrace  the immensity of the universe. We cannot form the idea of any innocent  and sensible being, whose happiness we should not desire, or to whose  misery, when distinctly brought home to the imagination, we should not  have some degree of aversion. The idea of a mischievous, though  sensible, being, indeed, naturally provokes our hatred: but the ill-will  which, in this case, we bear to it, is really the effect of our  universal benevolence. It is the effect of the sympathy which we feel  with the misery and resentment of those other innocent and sensible  beings, whose happiness is disturbed by its malice.This universal  benevolence, how noble and generous soever, can be the source of no  solid happiness to any man who is not thoroughly convinced that all  the inhabitants of the universe, the meanest as well as the greatest,  are under the immediate care and protection of that great, benevolent,  and all-wise Being, who directs all the movements of nature; and who is  determined, by his own unalterable perfections, to maintain in it, at  all times, the greatest possible quantity of happiness. To this  universal benevolence, on the contrary, the very suspicion of a  fatherless world, must be the most melancholy of all reflections; from  the thought that all the unknown regions of infinite and  incomprehensible space may be filled with nothing but endless misery and  wretchedness. All the splendour of the highest prosperity can never  enlighten the gloom with which so dreadful an idea must necessarily  over-shadow the imagination; nor, in a wise and virtuous  man, can all the sorrow of the most afflicting adversity ever dry up the  joy which necessarily springs from the habitual and thorough conviction  of the truth of the contrary system.

Smith goes on to further emphasise this view in TMSII.II.19:

In every part of the universe we  observe means adjusted with the nicest artifice to the ends which they  are intended to produce, and admire how everything is contrived for  advancing the two great purposes of nature, the support of the  individual and the propagation of the species…[and studying this leads  us to admire] the wisdom of man, which in reality is the wisdom of God.

This pursuance of self-interest is expected of man, that is his  destiny to the way he leads his life on earth but this in turn seems to  align his activity to the moral centre of the universe or God’s will.  Smith explains this by trying to account for the way things tend to  naturally fall into place through a sense of balance as in laws of  nature. So, behaving in the right manner for oneself which inadvertently  or otherwise benefit others, tends to be in line with the natural moral  law of the Universe. Smith uses the corollary of showing that if a  person does not look after his own welfare and his highest good as in  trying to be a responsible and reasonable member in an economy, or  society, he is not looked upon favourably as he may not be doing what is  right.

Smith does believe in altruism, but he prefers to justify it via a  grounded pragmatic approach in which people do not have to be motivated  to do good for its own sake. People would be more easily swayed to be  good citizens when they realize that helping themselves and a sense of  self-reliance is how they best serve society, and that in turn creates a  society that best serves their own interest.

When you now turn to WN written after the bedrock of Smith’s ideas had been established in TMS, his economic opus starts to make a lot more sense. WN is  a sprawling work with such variety of observations that it is easy to  take any passage out of context and say this supports a general view of  the world based on a peculiar view of Smith’s.

But what can hardly be doubted is that while Smith reiterates man’s  drive for self-interest, he contrasts it to the negative effects of  selfishness repeatedly throughout WN. Smith clearly condemns  those who tend towards greed and exploitation and insists on people  being treated decently and fairly. He states how grabby monopolists try  to undermine the interests of all others as in WN Book I.11.264 (bold and italics mine):

The interest of the dealers,  however, in any particular branch of trade or manufactures, is always in  some respects different from, and even opposite to, that of the public.  To widen the market and to narrow the competition, is always the  interest of the dealers. To widen the market may frequently be agreeable  enough to the interest of the public; but to narrow the competition  must always be against it, and can serve only to enable the dealers, by  raising their profits above what they naturally would be, to levy, for  their own benefit, an absurd tax upon the rest of their fellow-citizens.  The proposal of any new law or regulation of commerce which comes from  this order, ought always to be listened to with great precaution, and  ought never to be adopted till after having been long and carefully  examined, not only with the most scrupulous, but with the most  suspicious attention. It comes from an order of men, whose  interest is never exactly the same with that of the public, who have  generally an interest to deceive and even to oppress the public, and who accordingly have, upon many occasions, both deceived and oppressed it.

The passage speaks for itself despite attempts of those who have  wilfully obfuscated matters to present Smith as a creature from their  own black lagoon.

Furthermore, in what may be one of the most memorable passages in WN,  Smith describes the ghastly system of division of labour in a pin  making industry. While there seems some form of efficiency in this  mechanization of human beings as cogs in an industry, the dehumanization  of the process is noted by Smith. No doubt a great deal of mechanical  productivity ensues in a way, but the human cost of this so-called  productivity is questioned.

While Marx and Engels went the extra miles and were more impassioned  and dramatic in their portraiture of human exploitation and suffering  during the industrial boom of their time, it is hard to deny that  Smith’s insistence on human decency in economic growth may have urged  them to outdo him in what was wrong with Capitalism.

The humane aspect of Smith is something hardcore capitalists hardly  mention if they are even aware of it. After considering the moral  sentiments in his work, it becomes clear that Smith does not support the  belief by FM fantasists and hardcore capitalists that he is their guru.

We will finally ‘put paid’ to the false claims of Smith being the promoter of the FM and Capitalism in what follows.

[Credit: Credit:  Alfred Ford.]

That Invisible Thingamajig

Perhaps a key weapon of FM fantasists and hardcore capitalists has  been the abuse of arguably the most famous term in economics: the  “invisible hand”. It is an understatement to say that lots have been  said about it. But so much of it has been to fit ideological obsessions  of so many that an actual look at what Smith says reveals something  quite different altogether.

There are many takes on the Invisible Hand (IH). Four main types of  interpretations will be looked at. The generic meaning of the IH is what  is most cherished by the hardcore fantasists: that the IH shows that an  unregulated market (the FM) in which there is minimal or  non-interference from anyone (especially governments) provides a system  of automatic equilibrium and matching of DS (demand and supply) which  not only satisfies everyone but is for the highest benefit of all with  the greatest wealth creation possible.

And anytime anyone says “FM-Capitalism good, all else bad”: they  follow it up with the chant “Adam Smith-IH”. When you mention the social  consequences of Capitalism, the response is “don’t be a  communist/socialist”, ‘greed is good’, human cost etc. are just  ‘externalities’.

Sadly, this pathetic trite falsehood of what Smith meant with the IH  has been handed down generations via irresponsible economic instructors  to hapless students. Despite that, there have been useful contributions  as to what the IH is supposed to mean. But there are three other  interpretations which are quite interesting and deserve closer notice.

For the record, the IH in Smith appears thrice in his works first in The History of Astronomy (HA), next in TMS and finally, in WN.  These days, there seems to be a growing trend in economists trying to  distance themselves from overt FM fanaticism and capitalist trumpery. So  the current view among some economists seems to be that Smith’s use of  the IH is more a passing phenomena that is interesting at best, a bauble  at worst.

On to the three interpretations of which Gavin Kennedy’s Adam Smith and the Invisible Hand: From Metaphor to Myth sits happily in the extremity of its claims that the IH, if not just an  example of Smith’s wry humour, is but a random term given undue  attention. Kennedy starts off promisingly on how the IH is merely a  metaphor and shows that it is quite possible that Smith only intended  the term to emphasise a system that operates well on its own without  interference including any invisible assistance emanating from a  mystical or religious source.

Kennedy almost pulls off his attempt except that claiming the IH is  pure metaphor for the obvious actions of self-regulating human behaviour  does not quite work (as will examined later); and that he forgets,  after admitting the distinction, that there is a clear difference for  Smith between self-interest and selfishness.

There is the even more interesting reply to Kennedy by Daniel Klein In Adam Smith’s Invisible Hands: Comment on Gavin Kennedy. He prefers to see the “mystery” in Smith and not give in to the prosaic  justifications of Kennedy. But Klein believes that the IH is more to do  with explaining the self-regulating, cooperative activity that takes  place between people and which occurs naturally when tending to one’s  mutual interests.

Klein thinks that Smith’s ideas take place within a spontaneous order  of natural liberty that is unknowable in its particulars (part of the  delectable mystery). He insists that teachers of economics make clear to  students the wonder to be found within economic principles (while  implicitly making clear that there is no Divine Order behind any of  this). We will look at this later.

Klein then becomes like Kennedy in misreading Smith by stating that the IH in TMS is “a terrible muddle”. He strangely goes on to say that the IH occurrence in WN is less muddled but “not without its mysteries”. Neither is he sure if the IH is “a tag for the comparative merit of freedom”.

The only mystery here is how muddled economists are on what Smith said and what was meant by the IH.

But the most fascinating piece is by Paul Oslington called Divine Action, Providence and Adam Smith’s Invisible Hand .

Osilington starts off with how Isaac Newton’s ideas affected Smith who even wrote his HA due  to this influence. Newton, perhaps more than Einstein, believed that  God does not play dice with the universe and that providence allows for  natural laws to keep the universe in order. But irregular events in the  universe are also taken care of by special providence in that it allows  for Divine adjustments to take place and keep the natural order of  things. It is this aspect of special providence that is said to have  been adopted by Smith.

In HA Smith mentions how the regularity of natural events  like the sun rising and setting is hardly questioned by men during early  polytheistic times, but only irregular events are noted like meteor  sightings. The IH of Jupiter (king of the Roman gods) was not, says  Smith, seen as an influence in regular events (as they were taken for  granted); but some otherworldly influence comes into play in order to  explain irregular events (e.g., eclipses).

To Oslington, what this shows is that Smith was developing an idea to  explain how man comes to understand that all events, irregular or  otherwise in the cosmos, have divine order attached to it. This Smith  then goes on to develop fully in his later works.

In TMS, Smith talks about how a rich landowner cannot hoard  everything he has for himself without ensuring that those who serve him  have enough to live on as well, so that they can go on serving him. This  leads to the rich man sharing, led by the IH, what he has so as to  ensure everyone gains something, so that despite himself, he has helped  the rest of society.

Oslington explains it well as:

The hand here is working against  the rapacity of the rich, levelling out consumption, and maintaining the  stability of the system. Smith understands that the stability [of] a  market economy depends on a modicum of justice and not too obscenely  unequal a distribution of consumption. This is why the hand intervening  to restrain the consumption of the rich serves to maintain the stability  of the market system. In Smith’s providential scheme it is special  providence, balancing the general providential force of self interest in  markets (p 9).

[An effective piece that I had not seen till recently also supports  the view of divine influence in Smith; from the abstract: “Smith’s  social and economic philosophy is inherently theological and that his  entire model of social order is logically dependent on the notion of  God’s action in nature.” Please see “The Hidden Theology of Adam Smith” by Lisa Hill.]

The passage below in TMS is central to understanding Smith and his IH and how it is meant to be understood in its famous occurrence in WN. Here is the passage almost in full and in context — part IV Section 1 paragraphs 10-11 (bold and italics are mine):

And it is well that nature imposes  upon us in this manner. It is this deception which rouses and keeps in  continual motion the industry of mankind. It is this which first  prompted them to cultivate the ground, to build houses, to found cities  and commonwealths, and to invent and improve all the sciences and arts,  which ennoble and embellish human life; which have entirely changed the  whole face of the globe, have turned the rude forests of nature into  agreeable and fertile plains, and made the trackless and barren ocean a  new fund of subsistence, and the great high road of communication to the  different nations of the earth. The earth by these labours of mankind  has been obliged to redouble her natural fertility, and to maintain a  greater multitude of inhabitants. It is to no purpose, that the proud  and unfeeling landlord views his extensive fields, and without a thought  for the wants of his brethren, in imagination consumes himself the  whole harvest that grows upon them. The homely and vulgar proverb, that  the eye is larger than the belly, never was more fully verified than  with regard to him. The capacity of his stomach bears no proportion to  the immensity of his desires, and will receive no more than that of the  meanest peasant. The rest he is obliged to distribute among those, who  prepare, in the nicest manner, that little which he himself makes use  of, among those who fit up the palace in which this little is to be  consumed, among those who provide and keep in order all the different  baubles and trinkets, which are employed in the oeconomy of greatness;  all of whom thus derive from his luxury and caprice, that share of the  necessaries of life, which they would in vain have expected from his  humanity or his justice. The produce of the soil maintains at all times  nearly that number of inhabitants which it is capable of maintaining. The  rich only select from the heap what is most precious and agreeable.  They consume little more than the poor, and in spite of their natural  selfishness and rapacity, though they mean only their own conveniency,  though the sole end which they propose from the labours of all the  thousands whom they employ, be the gratification of their own vain and  insatiable desires, they divide with the poor the produce of all their  improvements. They are led by an invisible hand to  make nearly the same distribution of the necessaries of life, which  would have been made, had the earth been divided into equal portions  among all its inhabitants, and thus without intending it, without  knowing it, advance the interest of the society, and afford means to the  multiplication of the species. When Providence divided the  earth among a few lordly masters, it neither forgot nor abandoned those  who seemed to have been left out in the partition. These last too enjoy  their share of all that it produces. In what  constitutes the real happiness of human life, they are in no respect  inferior to those who would seem so much above them. In ease of body and  peace of mind, all the different ranks of life are nearly upon a level,  and the beggar, who suns himself by the side of the highway, possesses  that security which kings are fighting for.

IV.I.11

The same principle, the same love  of system, the same regard to the beauty of order, of art and  contrivance, frequently serves to recommend those institutions which  tend to promote the public welfare. When a patriot exerts himself for  the improvement of any part of the public police, his conduct does not  always arise from pure sympathy with the happiness of those who are to  reap the benefit of it. It is not commonly from a fellow-feeling with  carriers and waggoners that a public-spirited man encourages the mending  of high roads. When the legislature establishes premiums and other  encouragements to advance the linen or woollen manufactures, its conduct  seldom proceeds from pure sympathy with the wearer of cheap or fine  cloth, and much less from that with the manufacturer or merchant. The  perfection of police, the extension of trade and manufactures, are noble  and magnificent objects. The contemplation of them pleases us, and we  are interested in whatever can tend to advance them. They make part of  the great system of government, and the wheels of the political machine  seem to move with more harmony and ease by means of them. We take  pleasure in beholding the perfection of so beautiful and grand a system,  and we are uneasy till we remove any obstruction that can in the least  disturb or encumber the regularity of its motions. All constitutions  of government, however, are valued only in proportion as they tend to  promote the happiness of those who live under them. This is their sole use and end. From a certain spirit of system, however, from a certain love of art  and contrivance, we sometimes seem to value the means more than the end,  and to be eager to promote the happiness of our fellow-creatures,  rather from a view to perfect and improve a certain beautiful and  orderly system, than from any immediate sense or feeling of what they  either suffer or enjoy. There have been men of the greatest public  spirit, who have shown themselves in other respects not very sensible to  the feelings of humanity. And on the contrary, there have been men of  the greatest humanity, who seem to have been entirely devoid of public  spirit. Every man may find in the circle of his acquaintance instances  both of the one kind and the other. Who had ever less humanity, or more  public spirit, than the celebrated legislator of Muscovy? The social and  well-natured James the First of Great Britain seems, on the contrary,  to have had scarce any passion, either for the glory or the interest of  his country. Would you awaken the industry of the man who seems almost  dead to ambition, it will often be to no purpose to describe to him the  happiness of the rich and the great; to tell him that they are generally  sheltered from the sun and the rain, that they are seldom hungry, that  they are seldom cold, and that they are rarely exposed to weariness, or  to want of any kind. The most eloquent exhortation of this kind will  have little effect upon him. If you would hope to succeed, you must  describe to him the conveniency and arrangement of the different  apartments in their palaces; you must explain to him the propriety of  their equipages, and point out to him the number, the order, and the  different offices of all their attendants. If any thing is capable of  making impression upon him, this will. Yet all these things tend only to  keep off the sun and the rain, to save them from hunger and cold, from  want and weariness. In the same manner, if you would implant public  virtue in the breast of him who seems heedless of the interest of his  country, it will often be to no purpose to tell him, what superior  advantages the subjects of a well-governed state enjoy; that they are  better lodged, that they are better clothed, that they are better fed.  These considerations will commonly make no great impression. You will be  more likely to persuade, if you describe the great system of public  police which procures these advantages, if you explain the connexions  and dependencies of its several parts, their mutual subordination to one  another, and their general subserviency to the happiness of the  society; if you show how this system might be introduced into his own  country, what it is that hinders it from taking place there at present,  how those obstructions might be removed, and all the several wheels of  the machine of government be made to move with more harmony and  smoothness, without grating upon one another, or mutually retarding one  another’s motions. It is scarce possible that a man should  listen to a discourse of this kind, and not feel himself animated to  some degree of public spirit. He will, at least for the moment, feel  some desire to remove those obstructions, and to put into motion so  beautiful and so orderly a machine. Nothing tends so much to promote  public spirit as the study of politics, of the several systems of civil  government, their advantages and disadvantages, of the constitution of  our own country, its situation, and interest with regard to foreign  nations, its commerce, its defence, the disadvantages it labours under,  the dangers to which it may be exposed, how to remove the one, and how  to guard against the other. Upon this account political  disquisitions, if just, and reasonable, and practicable, are of all the  works of speculation the most useful. Even the weakest and the worst of  them are not altogether without their utility. They serve at least to  animate the public passions of men, and rouse them to seek out the means  of promoting the happiness of the society.

[Credit: Tom Tomorrow.]

II

What in summary does this important passage say:

  • The rich and wealthy usually are more selfishly inclined than  most and could hardly be bothered with the welfare of those less  fortunate.

  • But in order to stay their course they need to let  their serfs survive as well and so inadvertently or otherwise ensure  their serfs’ survival thereby benefiting the welfare of others.

  • In making this distribution of things to those lower in the food chain, the rich are led into this by the IH.

  • Man  proposes (as in the selfishness of the rich) but providence disposes,  as in the balance that ensures some form of fairness to the less well  off.

  • All humans want happiness and all are equal in that respect  of wanting peace and solace as well other than the illusory difference  produced by status and the master-slave relationship thereof.

  • With  a touch of irony, Smith says even a beggar sunning himself seems to  have as much, if not more, peace of mind than kings (who constantly  worry about who is about to do them in, etc.).

  • The balance and  seemingly smooth operation of the IH behind the adjustments in society  is the same kind of system that when it appears in the general  governance of society appeals to a sense of order and artistry which  humans have a bias for.

  • When someone supports the idea of good  governance and commerce in his society it is not always out of sympathy  for his fellow man.

  • People tend to be impressed with the smooth  automatic functioning of a state and all that takes place within it as  it resonates with a sense of balance, harmony and artistry in us.

  • While  we acknowledge that the purpose of government is to ensure citizens’  happiness, we tend to be more appreciative of the well-oiled functioning  of things rather than whether all of society benefits from this.

  • A  person is not so much concerned with what public policies etc. are for  the benefit of his fellow citizens as much as realizing the remarkable  way his society functions and how it is something that is wondrous and  (implicit in this) perhaps worthy of emulation by others: this makes him  interested to ensure the well-oiled functioning of his society.

  • If  the proper and effective operation of a country can be justified via  just, reasonable and practicable ways, people may be inspired to seek  the means of seeking the happiness of their society.

It is important to note that in TMS Smith seems to be saying four things:

First, that through sympathy with his fellow man and  through serving one’s self-interest a person tends to serve, often  times inadvertently, the interests of society.

Second, the above tends to happen because it is  aligned to a force of balance that resonates with the moral centre of  the universe which ensures regularity in human affairs. We usually don’t  question this but take it as a given, knowingly or otherwise.

Third, and importantly, even if an  irregularity occurs such as man serving his own selfish interests as  opposed to his self-interest, there is an IH that rebalances accordingly  to ensure that there is some form of redress and justice in  distribution to ensure that those exploited still manage to subsist.

Fourth, that people seem to be caught up more with  the artistry and smooth functioning of things (that is, regularity and  order) than whether society actually gains from this. And if this mode  of smooth operation can be justified in a manner of justice and  fairness, then people will buy into it and thereby, against their will  at times, end up benefiting society at large.

In many cases, we have experienced situations where people compare  one society and economy with another over an excellent transportation  system, well maintained public amenities, health and educational  facilities that are people friendly, etc. In most instances, we also  wonder why we can’t have what works smoothly and well in other countries  in our own, and are willing to ask or push for, or work towards  manifesting this in our own societies. In this, Smith has given an  accurate description of things which resonates with many of us today.

The third point on how the IH comes in to readjust  seeming irregularity in the general balance of things is consonant with  what Oslington claims it does in terms of special providence. But  Oslington does not mention clearly enough how the irregularity occurs:  it occurs because even selfishness vis-à-vis self-interest gets the  touch of natural re-balancing to even things out a little. In all this,  it appears Smith is far more consistent in his thinking on the IH than  many thought him to be.

When it comes to WN, Oslington mentions that special  providence also comes in again to ensure that despite greater profits  available through trade abroad, the merchant paradoxically keeps capital  at home thereby benefiting the home front. But as a close reading of  that particular passage in WN shows, Oslington and others are not quite right in thinking that is how the irregularity appears. The irregularity in WN in relation to the IH arises from the ambiguity in what Smith says (we will look at this).

But in case there is still some doubt as to the moral core and Divine  Order spiralling through Smith’s work, this brilliant passage with its  take on capital punishment must be looked at in TMS Book 2.II.19-III.27 (bold and italics mine). It also reiterates with consistency the idea running through TMS and WN in relation to special providence acting through irregularities in the world as in the case of the IH:

Upon some occasions, indeed, we  both punish and approve of punishment, merely from a view to the general  interest of society, which, we imagine, cannot otherwise be secured. Of  this kind are all the punishments inflicted for breaches of what is  called either civil police, or military discipline. Such crimes do not  immediately or directly hurt any particular person; but their remote  consequences, it is supposed, do produce, or might produce, either a  considerable inconveniency, or a great disorder in the society. A  centinel, for example, who falls asleep upon his watch, suffers death by  the laws of war, because such carelessness might endanger the whole  army. This severity may, upon many occasions, appear necessary, and, for  that reason, just and proper. When the preservation of an individual is  inconsistent with the safety of a multitude, nothing can be more just  than that the many should be preferred to the one. Yet this punishment,  how necessary soever, always appears to be excessively severe. The  natural atrocity of the crime seems to be so little, and the punishment  so great, that it is with great difficulty that our heart can reconcile  itself to it. Though such carelessness appears very blamable, yet the  thought of this crime does not naturally excite any such resentment, as  would prompt us to take such dreadful revenge. A man of humanity must  recollect himself, must make an effort, and exert his whole firmness and  resolution, before he can bring himself either to inflict it, or to go  along with it when it is inflicted by others. It is not, however, in  this manner, that he looks upon the just punishment of an ungrateful  murderer or parricide. His heart, in this case, applauds with ardour,  and even with transport, the just retaliation which seems due to such  detestable crimes, and which, if, by any accident, they should happen to  escape, he would be highly enraged and disappointed. The very different  sentiments with which the spectator views those different punishments,  is a proof that his approbation of the one is far from being founded  upon the same principles with that of the other. He looks upon the  centinel as an unfortunate victim, who, indeed, must, and ought to be,  devoted to the safety of numbers, but whom still, in his heart, he would  be glad to save; and he is only sorry, that the interest of the many  should oppose it. But if the murderer should escape from punishment, it  would excite his highest indignation, and he would call upon God to  avenge, in another world, that crime which the injustice of mankind had  neglected to chastise upon earth.

For it well deserves to be taken  notice of, that we are so far from imagining that injustice ought to be  punished in this life, merely on account of the order of society, which  cannot otherwise be maintained, that Nature teaches us to hope, and  religion, we suppose, authorises us to expect, that it will be punished,  even in a life to come. Our sense of its ill desert pursues it, if I  may say so, even beyond the grave, though the example of its punishment  there cannot serve to deter the rest of mankind, who see it not, who  know it not, from being guilty of the like practices here. The justice  of God, however, we think, still requires, that he should hereafter  avenge the injuries of the widow and the fatherless, who are here so  often insulted with impunity. In every religion, and in every  superstition that the world has ever beheld, accordingly, there has been  a Tartarus as well as an Elysium; a place provided for the punishment  of the wicked, as well as one for the reward of the just.

Nature, however, when she implanted the seeds of this irregularity in the human breast, seems, as upon all other occasions, to have intended the happiness and perfection of the species. If the hurtfulness of the design, if the malevolence of the affection,  were alone the causes which excited our resentment, we should feel all  the furies of that passion against any person in whose breast we  suspected or believed such designs or affections were harboured, though  they had never broke out into any action. Sentiments, thoughts,  intentions, would become the objects of punishment; and if the  indignation of mankind run as high against them as against actions; if  the baseness of the thought which had given birth to no action, seemed  in the eyes of the world as much to call aloud for vengeance as the  baseness of the action, every court of judicature would become a real  inquisition. There would be no safety for the most innocent and  circumspect conduct. Bad wishes, bad views, bad designs, might still be  suspected; and while these excited the same indignation with bad  conduct, while bad intentions were as much resented as bad actions, they  would equally expose the person to punishment and resentment. Actions,  therefore, which either produce actual evil, or attempt to produce it,  and thereby put us in the immediate fear of it, are by the Author of  nature rendered the only proper and approved objects of human punishment  and resentment. Sentiments, designs, affections, though it is from  these that according to cool reason human actions derive their whole  merit or demerit, are placed by the great Judge of hearts beyond the  limits of every human jurisdiction, and are reserved for the cognizance  of his own unerring tribunal. That necessary rule of justice, therefore,  that men in this life are liable to punishment for their actions only,  not for their designs and intentions, is founded upon this salutary and  useful irregularity in human sentiments concerning merit or demerit,  which at first sight appears so absurd and unaccountable. But  every part of nature, when attentively surveyed, equally demonstrates  the providential care of its Author, and we may admire the wisdom and  goodness of God even in the weakness and folly of man.

It is even of considerable  importance, that the evil which is done without design should be  regarded as a misfortune to the doer as well as to the sufferer. Man is  thereby taught to reverence the happiness of his brethren, to tremble  lest he should, even unknowingly, do any thing that can hurt them, and  to dread that animal resentment which, he feels, is ready to burst out  against him, if he should, without design, be the unhappy instrument of  their calamity. As, in the ancient heathen religion, that holy ground  which had been consecrated to some god, was not to be trod upon but upon  solemn and necessary occasions, and the man who had even ignorantly  violated it, became piacular from that moment, and, until proper  atonement should be made, incurred the vengeance of that powerful and  invisible being to whom it had been set apart; so, by the wisdom of  Nature, the happiness of every innocent man is, in the same manner,  rendered holy, consecrated, and hedged round against the approach of  every other man; not to be wantonly trod upon, not even to be, in  any respect, ignorantly and involuntarily violated, without requiring  some expiation, some atonement in proportion to the greatness of such  undesigned violation. A man of humanity, who accidentally, and without  the smallest degree of blamable negligence, has been the cause of the  death of another man, feels himself piacular, though not guilty. During  his whole life he considers this accident as one of the greatest  misfortunes that could have befallen him. If the family of the slain is  poor, and he himself in tolerable circumstances, he immediately takes  them under his protection, and, without any other merit, thinks them  entitled to every degree of favour and kindness. If they are in better  circumstances, he endeavours by every submission, by every expression of  sorrow, by rendering them every good office which he can devise or they  accept of, to atone for what has happened, and to propitiate, as much  as possible, their, perhaps natural, though no doubt most unjust  resentment, for the great, though involuntary, offence which he has  given them.

What Smith in essence is saying here is that most people while  understanding why capital punishment was meted out to the sentry who  falls asleep at his post, would still see it as an extreme measure. The  same people would have a sense of outrage that would support a capital  sentence on someone who commits a heinous crime like parricide, and in  our time, mass murder. People can be so enraged that they may also  believe such punishment to go beyond mortal realms to punishment in the  afterlife as some form of universal retribution.

But Smith says that this apparent inconsistency or irregularity in  views of people as to who deserves punishment is something that should  be determined not from their thoughts but by their actions. He believes  that if people were to judge others based on their thoughts and  potential for thinking evil as opposed to someone caught in the act of  enacting the thought, then there would be no end to inquisitions  throughout society. (This would be equivalent to a type of ‘thought  crime’ in Orwell’s Nineteen Eighty-Four).

Judgment of what happens in the human heart is not for man to make as  it is in the province of the Divine. Humans can look at actions and  determine the nature of them thereby making judgments on that. We can  judge on actions, but not on thoughts or we will want accounting for  every negative human thought even when it doesn’t result in any harm to  anyone. The sentry, though his intentions were not based on malice, is  judged based on the fact that his lack of alertness could have dire  consequences for all.

If there appears any irregularity in this aspect of human judgment  and thinking as to how people react to punishment, it is a good thing  which prevents ‘witch hunts’ and allows for some semblance of order in  society. To Smith this falling into place of things naturally despite  the irregularity in response to, for instance, capital punishment, is  due to the special providential adjustment of Divinity.

Smith is not proposing here a system of legal justice and how a  judiciary should work. He is commenting on the moral and social nature  of man in relation to the Divine and how we operate in our daily lives.

Then as is typical of Smith, he provides a countervailing view to  show that there are instances of intention in humans that must be  considered as in the case of someone who did not have intent to  cause suffering to others but does so as in accidentally causing  someone’s death. There is atonement that is necessary though he is not  culpable for what happened. The sanctity of a human being and his  innocence cannot be infringed upon under any circumstances especially  via some form of revenge.

In doing this, as he does in many instances, Smith does his best to  explore the complexities in human affairs and tries to show that they  are consistently taken care of via a kind of natural balance, harmony  and adjustment that takes place in the universe, world, and society  which is the underlying Divine Order for the good of all.

In using this approach, Smith seems to be allowing for the  rationalisation of how we act and react to things in line with the  architectonic of Divine Order.

All apparent irregularities are Divine ways of adjusting the  seemingly imperfect into perfection. That is principally the phenomenon  of the IH. There is hardly a coincidence in Smith using the phrase “as upon all other occasions” (“Nature, however, when she implanted the seeds of this irregularity in the human breast, seems, as upon all other occasions, to have intended the happiness and perfection of the species) relating to irregularity above from TMS with the mention of “as in many other cases” together with the operation of the IH in WN – as in the passage below.

In both cases, the occurrence of the IH as special providence making  adjustments for the good of all is a regular and natural phenomenon.

Now take a detailed look at the passage where perhaps the most famous term in economics finally appears in WN Book 4 chapter 2 (bold and italics are mine):

IV.2.1

By restraining, either by high  duties or by absolute prohibitions, the importation of such goods from  foreign countries as can be produced at home, the monopoly of the home  market is more or less secured to the domestic industry employed in  producing them. Thus the prohibition of importing either live cattle or  salt provisions from foreign countries secures to the graziers of Great  Britain the monopoly of the home market for butcher’s meat. The high  duties upon the importation of corn, which in times of moderate plenty  amount to a prohibition, give a like advantage to the growers of that  commodity. The prohibition of the importation of foreign woollens is  equally favourable to the woollen manufacturers. The silk manufacture,  though altogether employed upon foreign materials, has lately obtained  the same advantage. The linen manufacture has not yet obtained it, but  is making great strides towards it. Many other sorts of manufacturer  have, in the same manner, obtained in Great Britain, either altogether  or very nearly, a monopoly against their countrymen. The variety of  goods of which the importation into Great Britain is prohibited, either  absolutely, or under certain circumstances, greatly exceeds what can  easily be suspected by those who are not well acquainted with the laws  of the customs.

IV.2.2

That this monopoly of the  home-market frequently gives great encouragement to that particular  species of industry which enjoys it, and frequently turns towards that  employment a greater share of both the labour and stock of the society  than would otherwise have gone to it, cannot be doubted. But whether it  tends either to increase the general industry of the society, or to give  it the most advantageous direction, is not, perhaps, altogether so  evident.

IV.2.3

The general industry of the  society never can exceed what the capital of the society can employ. As  the number of workmen that can be kept in employment by any particular  person must bear a certain proportion to his capital, so the number of  those that can be continually employed by all the members of a great  society must bear a certain proportion to the whole capital of that  society, and never can exceed that proportion. No regulation of commerce  can increase the quantity of industry in any society beyond what its  capital can maintain. It can only divert a part of it into a direction  into which it might not otherwise have gone; and it is by no means  certain that this artificial direction is likely to be more advantageous  to the society than that into which it would have gone of its own  accord.

IV.2.4

Every individual is continually  exerting himself to find out the most advantageous employment for  whatever capital he can command. It is his own advantage, indeed, and  not that of the society, which he has in view. But the study of his own  advantage naturally, or rather necessarily, leads him to prefer that  employment which is most advantageous to the society.

IV.2.5

First, every individual endeavours  to employ his capital as near home as he can, and consequently as much  as he can in the support of domestic industry; provided always that he  can thereby obtain the ordinary, or not a great deal less than the  ordinary profits of stock.

IV.2.6

Thus, upon equal or nearly equal  profits, every wholesale merchant naturally prefers the home-trade to  the foreign trade of consumption, and the foreign trade of consumption  to the carrying trade. In the home-trade his capital is never so long  out of his sight as it frequently is in the foreign trade of  consumption. He can know better the character and situation of the  persons whom he trusts, and if he should happen to be deceived, he knows  better the laws of the country from which he must seek redress. In the  carrying trade, the capital of the merchant is, as it were, divided  between two foreign countries, and no part of it is ever necessarily  brought home, or placed under his own immediate view and command. The  capital which an Amsterdam merchant employs in carrying corn from  Konigsberg to Lisbon, and fruit and wine from Lisbon to Konigsberg, must  generally be the one half of it at Konigsberg and the other half at  Lisbon. No part of it need ever come to Amsterdam. The natural residence  of such a merchant should either be at Konigsberg or Lisbon, and it can  only be some very particular circumstances which can make him prefer  the residence of Amsterdam. The uneasiness, however, which he feels at  being separated so far from his capital generally determines him to  bring part both of the Konigsberg goods which he destines for the market  of Lisbon, and of the Lisbon goods which he destines for that of  Konigsberg, to Amsterdam: and though this necessarily subjects him to a  double charge of loading and unloading, as well as to the payment of  some duties and customs, yet for the sake of having some part of his  capital always under his own view and command, he willingly submits to  this extraordinary charge; and it is in this manner that every country  which has any considerable share of the carrying trade becomes always  the emporium, or general market, for the goods of all the different  countries whose trade it carries on. The merchant, in order to save a  second loading and unloading, endeavours always to sell in the  home-market as much of the goods of all those different countries as he  can, and thus, so far as he can, to convert his carrying trade into a  foreign trade of consumption. A merchant, in the same manner, who is  engaged in the foreign trade of consumption, when he collects goods for  foreign markets, will always be glad, upon equal or nearly equal  profits, to sell as great a part of them at home as he can. He saves  himself the risk and trouble of exportation, when, so far as he can, he  thus converts his foreign trade of consumption into a home-trade. Home  is in this manner the centre, if I may say so, round which the capitals  of the inhabitants of every country are continually circulating, and  towards which they are always tending, though by particular causes they  may sometimes be driven off and repelled from it towards more distant  employments. But a capital employed in the home-trade, it has already  been shown, necessarily puts into motion a greater quantity of domestic  industry, and gives revenue and employment to a greater number of the  inhabitants of the country, than an equal capital employed in the  foreign trade of consumption: and one employed in the foreign trade of  consumption has the same advantage over an equal capital employed in the  carrying trade. Upon equal, or only nearly equal profits, therefore,  every individual naturally inclines to employ his capital in the manner  in which it is likely to afford the greatest support to domestic  industry, and to give revenue and employment to the greatest number of  people of his own country.

IV.2.7

Secondly, every individual who  employs his capital in the support of domestic industry, necessarily  endeavours so to direct that industry that its produce may be of the  greatest possible value.

IV.2.8

The produce of industry is what it  adds to the subject or materials upon which it is employed. In  proportion as the value of this produce is great or small, so will  likewise be the profits of the employer. But it is only for the sake of  profit that any man employs a capital in the support of industry; and he  will always, therefore, endeavour to employ it in the support of that  industry of which the produce is likely to be of the greatest value, or  to exchange for the greatest quantity either of money or of other goods.

IV.2.9

But the annual revenue of every  society is always precisely equal to the exchangeable value of the whole  annual produce of its industry, or rather is precisely the same thing  with that exchangeable value. As every individual, therefore, endeavours  as much as he can both to employ his capital in the support of domestic  industry, and so to direct that industry that its produce may be of the  greatest value; every individual necessarily labours to render the  annual revenue of the society as great as he can. He generally,  indeed, neither intends to promote the public interest, nor knows how  much he is promoting it. By preferring the support of domestic to that  of foreign industry, he intends only his own security; and by  directing that industry in such a manner as its produce may be of the  greatest value, he intends only his own gain, and he is in this, as in many other cases, led by an invisible hand to promote an end which was no part of his intention. Nor is it always the worse for the society that it was no part of it. By  pursuing his own interest he frequently promotes that of the society  more effectually than when he really intends to promote it. I have never  known much good done by those who affected to trade for the public  good. It is an affectation, indeed, not very common among merchants, and very few words need be employed in dissuading them from it.

What in essence the passage says:

  1. Domestic industries can be protected by trade tariffs on imports.

  2. That  domestic monopolies may result due to this but government may be in  cahoots with local industries in doing so to the disadvantage of  citizens.

  3. That this tendency to profit taking via monopoly tends  to reallocate resources to serve monopolistic interests and the benefit  of which, to the country, is ambiguous.

  4. Some form of  interference can see to the reallocation of capital away from  monopolistic tendencies but it is uncertain as to the benefit that  arises from such moves.

  5. Individuals who seem to pursue self  interest in the way they allocate their capital may, in effect, actually  be benefiting society without their knowing.

  6. Merchants would on the whole prefer to keep capital at home because they can monitor its progress and gains better that way.

  7. This  results in the home country of a merchant engaged in export trade to  also having a variety of that produce sold there as long as some form of  profit taking can be managed in the process.

  8. Since most gain  seems to arise from deploying capital within the home country there is a  tendency for capital to be kept home which results in industry and  employment growing and revenues rising.

  9. Those who adopt this strategy will want to see that the produce of such industries be of the greatest value.

  10. In such a deployment of capital the merchant intends to gain the maximum profit he can.

  11. Through  such moves of maximizing profit the revenue in a country is increased  and the motivation behind this is not related to society’s benefitting  consciously or otherwise.

  12. By supporting domestic industry in this manner over foreign ones the merchant is only pursuing his own interest.

  13. Via this mode of operation he seems to be led by an IH to promote an end which was by no means his original intention.

  14. He. ends up promoting society’s interests more than he would have if his intention was to serve mainly society’s interests.

  15. Not much good arises from commercial transactions that are solely for society’s good.

It would be hard to prove that Smith does not here advocate keeping  capital at home as opposed to investing it overseas. But there is more  in all this than just that. This passage is one of many that are  ambiguous in WN. Yet within the ambiguity lies the special  providence that accounts for the irregularity that accompanies the use  of the IH. How does this ambiguity work?

From (1) – (3) we see that merchants are quite happy to exploit  cornering the domestic market to set up some form of monopoly aided by  government tariffs on imports. This is consistent with the reading of  selfishness (as opposed to self-interest) of those tending toward  monopolies. There is no doubt that Smith is against the selfishness that  stems from monopoly and greed as shown earlier with the quote on the  critical clash of interests in Book I.

But with (4) the transition to ambiguity begins as Smith says  interference to regulate some of this monopoly is not always  advantageous. In (5) the ambiguity comes full circle as Smith implies  that even with monopolistic ambition allocation of capital may be for  everyone’s good. This is the ambiguous merger of selfishness and  self-interest which can sometimes describe what does happen in reality.  The rest of the passage shows how the tendency to maximize profits  through favouring domestic to foreign industries leads to greater  produce, labour, and revenue for the home country.

So even if the merchant is driven by selfishness or a mixture of  self-interest and selfishness — hence the irregularity — the special  providence of the IH steps in to adjust things such that society gains  even when the intention of such societal good was not there in the first  place. This is consistent with the irregularity of selfishness in the TMS that also sees the IH adjust things such that everyone gains all round.

Not much good arises from commercial ventures that work consciously  to solely benefit everyone as an end in itself. So, it becomes clear  that there is a kind of teleology to Smith and a natural order to things in a Divinely guided universe with a moral centre:  that while self-interest ensures smooth functioning of things in a  society, the imbalance of selfishness is also readjusted into a kind of  balance that is in the end for the good of all.

This does not imply that overtly destructive activities like  rampant monopolies and the ills of capitalism as we know through  hindsight, and still live through today, will have the IH come in and  rescue everyone. There will be consequences for bad actions, and they are inescapable just as the consequences of war result in unimaginable human suffering.

Yet under Smith’s scheme of things, the broad architecture of the  universe with its Divine Order and moral centre will still see a balance  come into play, as life does go on albeit sometimes on quite a  different paradigm.

[Credit: Bob.]

III

And Justice For All

Back to another passage in TMS, where Smith writes in I.I.36 (bold and italics mine):

To see the emotions of their  hearts, in every respect, beat time to his own, in the violent and  disagreeable passions, constitutes his sole consolation. But he can only  hope to obtain this by lowering his passion to that pitch, in which the  spectators are capable of going along with him. He must flatten, if I  may be allowed to say so, the sharpness of its natural tone, in order to reduce it to harmony and concord with the emotions of those who are about him. What  they feel, will, indeed, always be, in some respects, different from  what he feels, and compassion can never be exactly the same with  original sorrow; because the secret consciousness that the change of  situations, from which the sympathetic sentiment arises, is but  imaginary, not only lowers it in degree, but, in some measure, varies it  in kind, and gives it a quite different modification. These two  sentiments, however, may, it is evident, have such a correspondence with  one another, as is sufficient for the harmony of society. Though they will never be unisons, they may be concords, and this is all that is wanted or required.

What this passage encapsulates is the sympathetic vibrations of  energy people tend to set up in relation to one another in functioning  together as a group of people or society. Emotions and thoughts are  adjusted through conscious or unconscious effort when collaboration and  consensus is being built to move things forward. A strident tone, no  matter how justified, tends to lose support, hence, the need to  “flatten…the sharpness” to get some form of harmony among people.  Consensus building is a good thing.

This is radically opposed to the rampant egoistic obsessions that  many ideas of Capitalism and the FM tend to promote. Smith’s ideas have  to do with people getting along not through compromising of values, but  by consensus building. Which also means it eschews insistence of things  through the barrel of a gun (and the ideologies that go with it).

Smith, in always trying to keep things real, makes it clear that the  process of consensus building, and cooperative ventures do not create  unisons so much as concords and that, indeed, is as good as it gets. It  is analogous, in a way, to unity in diversity, or vice versa. Individual  identities and ideas are kept but they are adjusted to see what in  common can get things working. This somehow resonates with most people’s  idea of democracy.

This does not imply being able to suddenly propose revolutionary  ideas that can shift paradigms to a new level, but on a closer look this  paradigm shift may be achieved through the use of persuasion, and  convincing others of how it benefits them individually etc. that result  in ideas for the good of all.

But as Smith says, even such irregularities from what can be seen as  regular peaceable behaviour between peoples is given balance and  readjustment which sees a reordering of society. Hence, the current  economic crisis sweeping the world which while causing so much problems  for us, is the cleansing process which will bring down the old, corrupt,  violence drenched past that will get us to work together inevitably to  issue in a new age of peace, harmony and prosperity which may also have  existed in other times not subject to the ‘officially’ promulgated  history of the world.

This process of building ideas up to principles that can be used or  applied throughout a society is a process of social constructivism that  in a way is in concord with that of the moral constructivism of Kant  and, almost without doubt, the political constructivism of Rawls.  Smith’s social constructivism allows his economic constructivism to take  place. The IH as a function of Divine teleology allows for social  processes to be generated thereby creating situations for economic  practices to be in concordance with them. Economic ideas come forward  for the good of the individual and society, and are balanced, fair and  just for all.

And then we will see that the Invisible Hand has been visible all along.

©2022 Sanjay Perera. All rights reserved.

[Top picture credit: Adam Smith; credit: Simply Charly.]

Share

Share this post

The invisible hand: The natural order of things

solemninvestigator.substack.com
Comments
TopNew

No posts

Ready for more?

© 2023 Sanjay Perera
Privacy ∙ Terms ∙ Collection notice
Start WritingGet the app
Substack is the home for great writing